Catálogo de publicaciones - libros
The Shaping of Arithmetic after C. F. Gauss's Disquisitiones Arithmeticae
Catherine Goldstein ; Norbert Schappacher ; Joachim Schwermer (eds.)
Resumen/Descripción – provisto por la editorial
No disponible.
Palabras clave – provistas por la editorial
Number Theory; Algebra; History of Mathematical Sciences
Disponibilidad
Institución detectada | Año de publicación | Navegá | Descargá | Solicitá |
---|---|---|---|---|
No detectada | 2007 | SpringerLink |
Información
Tipo de recurso:
libros
ISBN impreso
978-3-540-20441-1
ISBN electrónico
978-3-540-34720-0
Editor responsable
Springer Nature
País de edición
Reino Unido
Fecha de publicación
2007
Información sobre derechos de publicación
© Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2007
Cobertura temática
Tabla de contenidos
A Book in Search of a Discipline (1801–1860)
Catherine Goldstein; Norbert Schappacher
There are a few respects which Cantor’s, Dedekind’s, and Kronecker’s arithmetization programmes share, in spite of all their manifest incompatibility with respect to finitist or constructivist requirements. First, all three authors considered mathematics as a science with a clearly defined domain of objects: as mentioned before, Kronecker viewed mathematics as a natural science; Dedekind considered his analysis of continuity via cuts as expressing the essence of this concept; Cantor seems to have considered even his transfinite numbers as something that he discovered, rather than invented. For all three authors arithmetization reduced the irrational numbers to the rational — or all the way to natural — numbers whose existence was taken to be evident. Second, they all executed this reduction to elementary given objects in away that they considered naturally adequate for the problem at hand: for Kronecker, this meant indeterminates and congruences , for Dedekind grouping together sets of primary objects was just as naturally adequate a procedure as the consideration of series of rational numbers was to Cantor. The overall image that this suggests of the movement of arithmetization in the 1870s and 1880s is therefore that of a novel theory of objects that had formerly been understood in terms of extrinsic notions (magnitudes), this novel theory being founded on an independently accepted basis (the natural numbers), and proceeding with ingredients or methods deemed to be acceptable. From this point of view, arithmetization, in spite of all its novelty, appears not as an expression of modernity — indeed, as far as new objects were created, they were not purely formal, nor were they objectivized tools, but regularly formed from existing integers — but as a new type of solid building, erected on a traditional base in a controlled and supposedly innocuous and stable construction.
Our periodization has allowed us to isolate a transitional phase of arithmetization where Gaussian influence is detectible at least in two of the major authors. This influence operated via diverging fundamental positions (Kronecker’s constructivism vs. Dedekind’s completed infinites), but always in the direction of a novel but object-oriented rewriting of analysis. Gauss’s after-effect ended with the onset of purely set-theoretic, axiomatic or logicist approaches, i.e., at the same time as the Göttingen nostrified image of arithmetization took shape.
Part I - A Book’s History | Pp. 2-65
Several Disciplines and a Book (1860–1901)
Catherine Goldstein; Norbert Schappacher
I hope that the use of module multiplication in some measure simplifies Gauss’s theory of composition of forms. For example, it clarifies the difficult associativity property described and proved by Gauss in art. 240. Multiplication of modules is an associative binary operation, and this property easily translates into the property Gauss uses.
But, more importantly, I hope that by focussing attention on Gauss’s composition of actual forms — as opposed to equivalence classes of forms as in the modern theory — I have highlighted Gauss’s great achievement in giving a rigorous treatment of the composition of binary quadratic forms in the greatest possible generality.
His theory is “rigorous,” not only in the usual sense that it is mathematically convincing, but also in the literal sense that it makes great demands on the reader. The second kind of rigor has caused succeeding generation of mathematicians to devote some of their best efforts to avoiding it. But it is the first kind of rigor that makes Gauss the great master. It is based on his mastery of the computational structure of his subject and his ability to explain that structure in the most general circumstances. While they may seek to avoid the difficulties of Gauss’s theory, succeeding generations should never cease to admire it.
Part I - A Book’s History | Pp. 66-103
The and the Theory of Equations
Olaf Neumann
I hope that the use of module multiplication in some measure simplifies Gauss’s theory of composition of forms. For example, it clarifies the difficult associativity property described and proved by Gauss in art. 240. Multiplication of modules is an associative binary operation, and this property easily translates into the property Gauss uses.
But, more importantly, I hope that by focussing attention on Gauss’s composition of actual forms — as opposed to equivalence classes of forms as in the modern theory — I have highlighted Gauss’s great achievement in giving a rigorous treatment of the composition of binary quadratic forms in the greatest possible generality.
His theory is “rigorous,” not only in the usual sense that it is mathematically convincing, but also in the literal sense that it makes great demands on the reader. The second kind of rigor has caused succeeding generation of mathematicians to devote some of their best efforts to avoiding it. But it is the first kind of rigor that makes Gauss the great master. It is based on his mastery of the computational structure of his subject and his ability to explain that structure in the most general circumstances. While they may seek to avoid the difficulties of Gauss’s theory, succeeding generations should never cease to admire it.
Part II - Algebraic Equations, Quadratic Forms, Higher Congruences: Key Mathematical Techniques of the | Pp. 107-127
Composition of Binary Quadratic Forms and the Foundations of Mathematics
Harold M. Edwards
I hope that the use of module multiplication in some measure simplifies Gauss’s theory of composition of forms. For example, it clarifies the difficult associativity property described and proved by Gauss in art. 240. Multiplication of modules is an associative binary operation, and this property easily translates into the property Gauss uses.
But, more importantly, I hope that by focussing attention on Gauss’s composition of actual forms — as opposed to equivalence classes of forms as in the modern theory — I have highlighted Gauss’s great achievement in giving a rigorous treatment of the composition of binary quadratic forms in the greatest possible generality.
His theory is “rigorous,” not only in the usual sense that it is mathematically convincing, but also in the literal sense that it makes great demands on the reader. The second kind of rigor has caused succeeding generation of mathematicians to devote some of their best efforts to avoiding it. But it is the first kind of rigor that makes Gauss the great master. It is based on his mastery of the computational structure of his subject and his ability to explain that structure in the most general circumstances. While they may seek to avoid the difficulties of Gauss’s theory, succeeding generations should never cease to admire it.
Part II - Algebraic Equations, Quadratic Forms, Higher Congruences: Key Mathematical Techniques of the | Pp. 129-144
Composition of Quadratic Forms: An Algebraic Perspective
Della D. Fenster; Joachim Schwermer
There are many ways to measure the reception — and success — of a text, or, more precisely, the ideas of a text. We have elaborated here, in part, on Martin Kneser’s personal remarks and contributions at Oberwolfach, in June 2001. That Gauss’s question on the composition of forms could lead to the construction of a complex, yet stunningly elegant, algebraic theory of composition for binary quadratic modules over an arbitrary commutative ring with unity certainly testifies — again — to the breadth and depth of Gauss’s original ideas. Hurwitz’s private thoughts on Gauss’s composition of forms at the close of the nineteenth century, Bhargava’s more contemporary results on the arithmetic of number fields and Kneser’s extension of the theory via Clifford algebras provide further evidence of the lasting impact of the .
Part II - Algebraic Equations, Quadratic Forms, Higher Congruences: Key Mathematical Techniques of the | Pp. 145-158
The Unpublished Section Eight: On the Way to Function Fields over a Finite Field
Günther Frei
I hope that the use of module multiplication in some measure simplifies Gauss’s theory of composition of forms. For example, it clarifies the difficult associativity property described and proved by Gauss in art. 240. Multiplication of modules is an associative binary operation, and this property easily translates into the property Gauss uses.
But, more importantly, I hope that by focussing attention on Gauss’s composition of actual forms — as opposed to equivalence classes of forms as in the modern theory — I have highlighted Gauss’s great achievement in giving a rigorous treatment of the composition of binary quadratic forms in the greatest possible generality.
His theory is “rigorous,” not only in the usual sense that it is mathematically convincing, but also in the literal sense that it makes great demands on the reader. The second kind of rigor has caused succeeding generation of mathematicians to devote some of their best efforts to avoiding it. But it is the first kind of rigor that makes Gauss the great master. It is based on his mastery of the computational structure of his subject and his ability to explain that structure in the most general circumstances. While they may seek to avoid the difficulties of Gauss’s theory, succeeding generations should never cease to admire it.
Part II - Algebraic Equations, Quadratic Forms, Higher Congruences: Key Mathematical Techniques of the | Pp. 159-198
A Network of Scientific Philanthropy: Humboldt’s Relations with Number Theorists
Herbert Pieper
I hope that the use of module multiplication in some measure simplifies Gauss’s theory of composition of forms. For example, it clarifies the difficult associativity property described and proved by Gauss in art. 240. Multiplication of modules is an associative binary operation, and this property easily translates into the property Gauss uses.
But, more importantly, I hope that by focussing attention on Gauss’s composition of actual forms — as opposed to equivalence classes of forms as in the modern theory — I have highlighted Gauss’s great achievement in giving a rigorous treatment of the composition of binary quadratic forms in the greatest possible generality.
His theory is “rigorous,” not only in the usual sense that it is mathematically convincing, but also in the literal sense that it makes great demands on the reader. The second kind of rigor has caused succeeding generation of mathematicians to devote some of their best efforts to avoiding it. But it is the first kind of rigor that makes Gauss the great master. It is based on his mastery of the computational structure of his subject and his ability to explain that structure in the most general circumstances. While they may seek to avoid the difficulties of Gauss’s theory, succeeding generations should never cease to admire it.
Part III - The German Reception of the Institutions and Ideas | Pp. 201-233
‘O Θɛòζ’ Aριθμηίíξɛι: The Rise of Pure Mathematics as Arithmetic with Gauss
José Ferreirós
I hope that the use of module multiplication in some measure simplifies Gauss’s theory of composition of forms. For example, it clarifies the difficult associativity property described and proved by Gauss in art. 240. Multiplication of modules is an associative binary operation, and this property easily translates into the property Gauss uses.
But, more importantly, I hope that by focussing attention on Gauss’s composition of actual forms — as opposed to equivalence classes of forms as in the modern theory — I have highlighted Gauss’s great achievement in giving a rigorous treatment of the composition of binary quadratic forms in the greatest possible generality.
His theory is “rigorous,” not only in the usual sense that it is mathematically convincing, but also in the literal sense that it makes great demands on the reader. The second kind of rigor has caused succeeding generation of mathematicians to devote some of their best efforts to avoiding it. But it is the first kind of rigor that makes Gauss the great master. It is based on his mastery of the computational structure of his subject and his ability to explain that structure in the most general circumstances. While they may seek to avoid the difficulties of Gauss’s theory, succeeding generations should never cease to admire it.
Part III - The German Reception of the Institutions and Ideas | Pp. 234-268
From Reciprocity Laws to Ideal Numbers: An (Un)Known Manuscript by E.E. Kummer
Reinhard Bölling
The conquest of several mathematical areas by arithmetic, which we mentioned in the introduction, was thus achieved through two rival ways, both stemming from Gauss’s work. The first one, followed by Weierstrass, Dedekind and Cantor, borrowed the conception of number from Gauss. This conception entailed a development of mathematics through the of this concept of number and the introduction of new numbers. At the close of the conquest, which was to lead, in particular, to the arithmetization of analysis, “the captive analysis captured its savage victor,” and arithmetic was reduced to a simple province of analysis. The second way, followed by Kronecker who rejected this annexation of arithmetic by analysis, borrowed other concepts and methods, also from Gauss. These concepts, more related to operations than to objects, had to avoid the extension of the concept of number and the proliferation of new numbers. Thus Kronecker proposed this deployment of operations as an alternative to the development of the mathematical subject matter through conceptual extension. These two approaches — conceptual extension (and the consequent widening of the domain of objects) or operative deployment — appear more generally as distinct paths to mathematical progress. These two ways, usually coming one after the other, are combined in Gauss’s work. Thus this work stops the pendular swing from the concept (or the object) to the operation and vice versa.
Part IV - Complex Numbers and Complex Functions in Arithmetic | Pp. 270-290
Elliptic Functions and Arithmetic
Christian Houzel
We have tried to showthe beginnings of the intervention of the theory of elliptic functions in arithmetic: complex multiplication, -calculus, and the functional equation for the theta functions, Kronecker’s limit formula, addition theorem and Diophantine analysis. The germs of most of these ideas were already present in Gauss’s work. Gauss clearly saw the necessity to use methods not restricted to the consideration of natural numbers, in order to prove properties of natural numbers.
After Abel and Jacobi, the mathematicians who developed these theories in the first two thirds of the XIX century were Eisenstein, Kronecker, and Hermite. We saw the particular importance of Kronecker’s work which vindicates this author’s insistence on formulae as the essence of mathematics.
At the end of the XIX century, and throughout the XX century, the theories mentioned have continually developed and this growth continues to this day. This is a testimony to the continuing presence of Gauss’s work.
Part IV - Complex Numbers and Complex Functions in Arithmetic | Pp. 291-312